Two of my main provisional findings to date have been that a) an Einstein-like clock adjustment procedure using signals of any kind is a synchronization procedure if and only if the conditions in which the signals are emitted and propagate are symmetrical in opposite directions; and b) the clock adjustment procedure using light signals set out by Einstein in his famous 1905 article is therefore not a synchronization procedure in every frame of reference, as explained in detail in a previous post.
The apparently widespread belief that Einstein's 1905 clock adjustment procedure is a synchronization procedure has led some physicists to draw spectacular but misguided conclusions on issues such as causality and existence. These conclusions are the result of what I will call the "simultaneity syndrome" in modern physics: the continued and uncritical application of concepts depending on synchronization, such as one-way speed, causality and distant simultaneous existence, in the framework of a theory in which clocks have not in fact been synchronized.
My first example is a passage in Wolfgang Rindler's textbook Relativity - Special, General and Cosmological (2001), in which the author suggests that superluminal signals cannot exist since they would give rise to intractable causality paradoxes (pp. 54-56). When I first read this passage, it didn't seem right to me because superluminal signals are logically perfectly conceivable while true causality paradoxes are not. Therefore, superluminal signals could not possibly give rise to such paradoxes.
But I didn't know where the flaw in Rindler's reasoning was. Today I think I know that his argument is a case of simultaneity syndrome.
Rindler says that if P is the event of sending out a signal along the x-axis of a first frame of reference S at superluminal speed U and L the event of that signal arriving somewhere else, then there are other frames, for example S', "in which L precedes P, in which cause and effect are thus reversed and in which the signal is considered to travel in the opposite spatial direction". "So, if L were, for example, the breaking of a glass somehow caused in S by the signal from P, then in S' the glass would break spontaneously and at the same time emit a signal to P. Since in macro-physics no such uncaused events are observed, nature must have a way to prevent superluminal signals."
Let me analyse the sequence of events sketched out by Rindler in greater detail. Suppose that S is a frame in which light signals propagate in symmetrical conditions in all directions and that thus Einstein's clock adjustment procedure can be used to synchronize clocks in S. Suppose further that Rindler's signal is an arrow which is initially stationary at x = 0 in S and then fired from (x; t) = (0; 0) in the positive direction of the x-axis at the superluminal speed of U = 2x1018 m/s. Suppose further that S' and S are in standard configuration - i.e. the events (0; 0) in the two frames coincide - and that S' moves at the speed of 9m/s relative to S. Finally, suppose the glass is a strong glass wall located at x' = 100m in S' and that the arrow gets lodged in it upon impact. From the point of view of S, we thus have the following situation at t = 0:
Diagram 1
In this diagram, an Einstein-adjusted S' clock at the glass wall would show a time of about
-10-16s. If the arrow is now fired from (0; 0) in S at the speed U, it will hit the glass wall when the S' clock there shows about -0.5x10-16s, i.e. in terms of S' coordinates the arrow arrives "before it was fired". In reality, of course, it arrives after it was fired, as it must, it's just that the clock located at 100m in S' is not synchronized with the one at 0m in S'. A diagram of the arrow's progress in terms of S' coordinates shows what happens if we treat those coordinates as if they defined a relationship of simultaneity:
Diagram 2 - I have exaggerated the angle between the incoming world line of the arrow and the t'-axis for clarity
In this diagram, at the time t' = -0.5x10-16s in S', while the arrow is still lodged in the firing mechanism and moves at -9m/s towards the (0; 0) position in S', a copy of the arrow mysteriously pops up from nowhere at 100m and instantly splits into two arrows, one of which remains lodged in the glass while the other moves backwards towards the arrow firing mechanism, where it merges with the first copy just as the arrow is fired at (0; 0). All this is of course nonsense, resulting from the application of the language of simultaneity to a situation in which clocks are not synchronized. Trying to make sense of the diagram in terms of "simultaneity" and "cause and effect" is like trying to make sense of a text in which words have been strung together arbitrarily. It means trying to find meaning where there is no meaning. It is an example of simultaneity syndrome.
As Rindler points out, in the framework of SR "superluminal" signals could even be used to tamper with the past in one and the same location. The arrow could, for example, be plucked out of the glass wall in S', hurled back towards the arrow firing mechanism at "superluminal speed" in S' and hit and destroy that same arrow before it was even fired! People in S and S' would be left with two broken arrows, a shattered glass wall and a lot of unanswered questions. Rindler is right to say that this kind of scenario is fraught with paradox. But it does not follow from this, as he suggests, that superluminal signals cannot exist. It merely follows, much less spectacularly, that faster-than-instantaneous signals cannot exist. There may, of course, be physical barriers to any signal moving faster than light, at least locally. However, the idea that superluminal signals could create time paradoxes is based on the misguided belief that in special relativity Einstein-adjusted clocks in any particular frame of reference are necessarily synchronized and all "speeds" are meaningful.
The simultaneity syndrome strikes again in Vesselin Petkov's book Relativity and the Nature of Spacetime (2005), where it leads to astounding conclusions about simultaneous existence.
Petkov argues that the indisputable empirical validity of special relativity means that we live in a four-dimensional "block universe" in which the flow of time is just an illusion since in SR every event exists simultaneously with every other in some frame of reference (see for example pp. 123-134). In a blog post published in May 2008, Sabine Hossenfelder pretty much hit the nail on the head when she said that Petkov's argument is wrong because "existence" is not a concept that is part of SR, so "everything that can be said about 'existence' in SR is a completely empty statement". I'd add that the reason why SR has nothing to say about distant simultaneous existence is that clocks in SR are in general not synchronized.
What these examples show is that, for a proper understanding of special relativity, it is crucial to realize that Einstein's clock adjustment procedure is not a synchronization procedure. Once this has been understood, everything else falls into place:
- the principle of the constancy of the "speed of light", for example, since it becomes clear that the "speed" it refers to is a purely formal "coordinate speed" obtained from clocks which are not necessarily synchronized;
- or the "time quakes" which occur in SR when distant observers begin to move relative to each other, since, again, the only "time" that is subjected to such swings is a purely formal "coordinate time" shown by clocks which are not synchronized.
To illustrate once again the effects of adjusting clocks in ways which do not synchronize them, take the case of two runners who set off from the mid-point between two clocks at the same time and who set those distant clocks to the same time when they arrive there. If they were equally good runners, equally well motivated, rested and fed, making equal efforts, traversing equally difficult terrain in equal weather conditions and so on, we might be willing to consider that their clock adjustment has probably roughly synchronized those clocks.
If, on the other hand, one of them sprinted to her clock and the other took a leisurely stroll, we would not regard those two clocks as synchronized and it would not be possible to measure one-way speeds using such clocks. If we did so in purely formal terms for people walking from one clock to the other, by dividing the distance between the clocks by the difference in clock readings, we'd get nonsensical results, such as "infinitely fast" or even "faster-than-infinite" walking speeds.
Those clocks would not be synchronized because, in abstract terms, the conditions in which the signals used are emitted or propagate are not symmetrical. And that's exactly why, in general, clocks in SR are not synchronized, either. The idea that we could define simultaneity by declaring that those clocks are to be regarded as synchronized "by definition" reminds me of an often-quoted passage in Lewis Carroll's Through the Looking-Glass (1871), in which Humpty Dumpty declares: "When I use a word, it means just what I choose it to mean - neither more nor less." It doesn't, of course, and it would take more than the choice of the entire community of physicists to make true Werner Heisenberg's suggestion, in his book Physics and Philosophy published in 1958, that "language" has already evolved in such a way that today "the word 'simultaneous' is used in line with the definition given by Einstein" (p. 163).
As I have attempted to show, the truth is that even contemporary specialists on relativity, such as Rindler and Petkov, use the concept of simultaneity in a rather confused and confusing way. If that is so, how do they explain the principle of the constancy of the speed of light to their readers? And how do they tease out the role of definition, stipulation or convention in that principle? My next post will tell.
Max Jammer has written a "comprehensive" survey of Concepts of Simultaneity - From Antiquity to Einstein and Beyond (2006), most of which is in fact devoted to Einstein's definition of simultaneity and subsequent debates relating to it. On reading this book, it is striking that apparently those debates have almost exclusively centred on the question of whether or not Einstein's clock adjustment procedure is the only possible way to synchronize clocks rather than whether or not it is a synchronization procedure in the first place. Attentive readers will have noticed that in my view the latter question is much more relevant for an understanding of Special Relativity and the principle of the constancy of c.
In particular, if Jammer is to be believed, the entire global community of physicists and philosophers seems to have completely ignored the requirement that the conditions in which an Einstein clock adjustment signal is emitted or propagates must be symmetrical in opposite directions. With one notable exception: one fairly prominent physicist did realize the importance of this requirement and wrote it down a few years after Einstein published his famous 1905 article. His name was... Albert Einstein!
In fact, as Jammer's book shows, Einstein was perfectly aware of the need for symmetrical conditions of signal emission and propagation for his clock adjustment procedure to qualify as a synchronization procedure. In an article on "The Principle of Relativity and its Consequences in Modern Physics" first published in French in 1910, and quoted in Jammer's book on page 124, Einstein writes that the "means of sending signals" in his clock adjustment procedure "must be such that we have no reason to believe that the phenomena of signal transmission in the direction AB differ in any way from the phenomena of signal transmission in the direction BA".
In view of the importance of this quote, I consulted The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein - Volume 3 (1993), in which the original article in French, "Le principe de relativité et ses conséquences dans la physique moderne", published in Archives des sciences physiques et naturelles 29 (1910) pp. 5-28 and 125-144, is reproduced. And I translated the passage myself since the English translation quoted by Jammer inaccurately says "should be such" when the French clearly says "doit être tel" - "must be such" (p. 25).
So, at least according to the French translation of the original manuscript, in Einstein's view this is an essential condition, a "must". Well, I agree... but unfortunately Einstein, having seen the light, fails to carry through this thought to its logical conclusion. Far from realizing that, if the condition is fulfilled in one frame of reference, it cannot possibly be fulfilled for the very same light signals in a second frame of reference that moves relative to the first, Einstein argues that the equivalence of the conditions of light emission and propagation in all directions in any frame is true "by definition" since "the principle of the constancy of the speed of light" ensures that "in empty space, light always propagates at the speed c" (p. 26).
This argument, which is akin to a line of reasoning put forward by Max Born as set out in my previous post, is flawed because a synchronization procedure must be established before a principle such as the constancy of the speed of light in opposite directions even makes sense. Of course, it may be possible to adjust clocks in such a way that, in purely formal terms, the equality of the speed of light in different directions is ensured for every observer, and this is indeed what Einstein did. It remains that such a clock adjustment procedure is not necessarily a synchronization procedure, which logically has to be established before meaningful, rather than purely formal, statements about the constancy of the one-way speed of light in different directions can be made.
After all this, little remains to be said about Allan Janis's online article on the Conventionality of Simultaneity. Apart from a brief discussion of possible causal anomalies in Special Relativity, essentially that article, too, discusses the issue of whether or not Einstein's clock adjustment procedure is the only possible way to synchronize clocks, rather than whether or not that procedure is a synchronization procedure in the first place.
Perhaps the apparent near-absence of debate on such a crucial aspect of the constancy of the speed of light for every observer, and thus of Special Relativity as a whole, should make me stop in my tracks. If all physicists and philosophers agree that Einstein's clock adjustment procedure is a synchronization procedure, who am I to question it? Are physicists not free to synchronize clocks as they see fit, even if that means departing from previous concepts of simultaneity, which they may have come to find unworkable or inconvenient? The answer will have to wait until my next post.
One of the few attempts to justify Einstein's clock adjustment procedure that I have seen in the literature is contained in a book by Max Born, Einstein's Theory of Relativity, first published in German in 1920. New editions were published in English in 1962 and in German in 1964.
In the 1964 edition, Born describes a clock adjustment procedure which is essentially equivalent to that presented by Einstein in his 1905 article: clocks in A and B in a uniformly moving frame of reference are adjusted to show the same time when a flash of light emanating from the midpoint C of a straight line between A and B reaches the clocks. Born notes that, if sound signals rather than light signals are used, this procedure results in disagreements between different frames of reference over which events are simultaneous. He adds that, in the case of sound, only the frame of reference that is at rest relative to the body of air in which the sound propagates has the right time, but no such distinction can be made if light signals are used 'because absolute movement relative to the light ether is a concept which, according to all our experience, has no physical reality'.
Born concludes that the procedure can be applied in any frame of reference using light signals. But since light signals observe the same no-overtaking rule as sound signals, the same kinds of disagreement arise, in other words 'if two such frames moving uniformly and in a straight line relative to each other meet and, for example, the clocks A and A' show the same time, then the hands of clocks B and B' will be in different positions. Both frames are equally entitled to claim that they have the right time, for each can maintain that it is at rest because all laws of nature are the same in both frames. But if two are equally entitled to make the same claim, which by its very nature can only be granted to one, then we must conclude that the claim is in fact meaningless: There is no absolute simultaneity. Once this has been grasped, it is difficult to understand that many centuries of exact research had to pass before this simple fact was recognized.' (pp. 197-98)
Born is right to say that, if a light ether existed, Einstein's clock adjustment procedure would not constitute a synchronization procedure in all frames of reference. However, the absence of an ether does not mean that Einstein's clock adjustment constitutes a synchronization procedure. This is because the real test for the usability of Einstein's clock adjustment procedure as a synchronization procedure is not whether or not there is a universal medium in which the signals propagate but, much more generally, whether or not the conditions in which the signals are emitted or propagate are symmetrical in opposite directions.
Whatever those signals are - waves in a universal medium; particles that are ejected without the need for a medium; or something else - it is clear that if the conditions of emission and propagation are symmetrical in opposite directions in one frame of reference, then they cannot also be symmetrical for the very same signals from the point of view of an observer who is moving relative to that frame of reference.
It is true that, if we don't know whether those conditions are symmetrical in two given frames of reference, then those two frames are equally entitled, or rather equally ill-placed, to claim that they have the right time if their clocks are Einstein-adjusted. But it does not follow that 'having the right time' is meaningless, it just means that we do not have sufficient information to decide which, if any, of the frames really does have the right time.
Perhaps Born's argument is that such information is unobtainable in principle because the laws of nature do not contain any parameter expressing any lack of symmetry in the propagation of light. This is an important point which requires further analysis.
First, it should be emphasized that in this context the "laws of nature" can only refer to laws that do not rely on the concept of distant simultaneity, since this is the very concept Born is seeking to define. In particular, the constancy of the one-way speed of light is not included in those laws.
Second, the relevant laws of nature are to a large extent based on observations and experiments in terrestrial laboratories, in which the conditions in which light is emitted and propagates may well be constant, and this may be the reason why those laws do not contain any parameter determining the presence or absence of symmetry.
For example, according to a more modern theory of light propagation than the ether model, electromagnetic radiation can be regarded as outwardly propagating disturbances in the electric fields of charged particles. Such disturbances may, for example, be caused by sudden, local accelerations of those particles - see for example Lesson 4 in this document by Daniel V. Schroeder. In this model, any light source carries the field in which the light propagates around with itself. Light emitted by a source that is stationary on Earth thus propagates in constant and quite possibly broadly symmetrical conditions in different directions, regardless of, for example, the position of the Earth in its orbit around the sun.
The "local acceleration history" of a source of light could thus be a parameter which is missing from the laws of nature as currently formulated and which may help to determine whether or not the conditions in which light propagates in opposite directions from that source are symmetrical.
Nevertheless, it may well be that from the point of view of a charge that has undergone local acceleration, for example as a result of a collision, everything still looks symmetrical in its new frame of reference and that thus "local acceleration history" is not directly observable. Worse, it may be difficult or impossible to reconstruct such acceleration histories if we do not already have a frame of reference which we know to be symmetrical and which we can thus use to define simultaneity.
If that is so - and I will have to look into these issues in much greater detail in subsequent posts on alternative definitions and theories that are compatible with observation and experiment - then Einstein's clock adjustment procedure may be justified on pragmatic grounds as a procedure that yields simple laws and enables accurate predictions, as long as it is made clear that it is not a synchronization procedure.
In summary, Born raises an important issue, which is the detectability of asymmetrical conditions in the emission or propagation of light, although he only does so in relation to the outmoded ether theory of light. His point that there may be no practical alternative to Einstein's clock adjustment procedure if there is no such detectability deserves careful consideration. On the other hand, Born fails to make a convincing case for the claim that Einstein's clock adjustment procedure is a synchronization procedure in all uniformly moving frames of reference.
So, what led Born to believe that Einstein's clock adjustment procedure can function as a synchronization procedure? I think the main reason is that he took it for granted that the one-way speed of light is constant for all observers. As he puts it at the start of his chapter on simultaneity, 'experience teaches us that the speed of light always has the same value c, regardless of the state of motion of the observer', and this fact requires us to drop 'the principles of defining space and time as they have always been applied until now'. (p. 194) In reality, of course, defining space and time, and in particular distant simultaneity, is a step that comes before experience can tell us anything about the constancy of c for all observers.
Born's approach of using the constancy of c as his starting point is reminiscent of Einstein's desire to adjust clocks in such a way that Maxwell's laws, and thus the constancy of c, are valid in all frames of reference. Neither of these physicists seems to have been interested primarily in exploring how clocks need to be adjusted in order to arrive at a meaningful definition of simultaneity. The result, I fear, is a theory in which clocks are not synchronized and consequently concepts that rely on synchronization, such as distant simultaneity, one-way speed and causality, break down.
Einstein's and Born's writings thus raise an intriguing possibility: that the strangeness of special relativity does not correspond to anything in the observed phenomena but is purely the result of a clock adjustment procedure which is not a synchronization procedure. In other words, the world may not actually be half as weird as a superficial reading of some physics books might suggest.
For now, however, this is merely a hypothesis which requires further testing against some of the more recent specialized literature on time and simultaneity in physics, starting with writings on these issues by Max Jammer and Allen Janis - in my next post.
How did Einstein justify his clock adjustment procedure using light signals? And how did he justify the idea that it represents a synchronization procedure not just in some frames of reference but in any frame in which the laws of mechanics hold?
These questions are important because some of the strangest claims of special relativity - as detailed in my previous post - are a direct result of Einstein's clock adjustment procedure and the idea that it represents a synchronization procedure in all such frames of reference.
In his 1905 article "On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies", Einstein set out a clock adjustment procedure which, according to him, invariably results in synchronized clocks in separate locations.
According to Einstein (p. 894), a time that is common to a location A in a coordinate system in which Newton's laws of mechanics hold and a location B in the same coordinate system can be defined 'by stipulating by definition that the time it takes for light to travel from A to B is the same as the time it takes for it to travel from B to A. For, let a ray of light leave A at "A time" tA in the direction of B, let it be reflected in B at "B time" tB in the direction of A and let it arrive back in A at "A time" t'A. The two clocks are defined to be synchronous if
tB – tA = t'A – tB. … '
What Einstein describes here is how, given a first clock in location A, a light signal can be used to adjust a second clock in location B such that the signal arrival time in B lies in the middle between the signal departure and arrival times in A. Einstein then effectively says that clocks adjusted in this way can be declared to be synchronous as a matter of definition. He thus suggests that there is no substance to the concept of simultaneity other than the existence of some systematic procedure to adjust distant clocks.
This position is made more explicit in Einstein's 1916 book, in which he approvingly cites a fictitious participant in a dialogue on simultaneity as saying: "There is only one demand to be made of the definition of simultaneity, namely, that in every real case it must supply us with an empirical decision as to whether or not the conception that has to be defined is fulfilled."
In these writings, Einstein thus fails to distinguish between clock adjustment procedures, which may indeed be chosen arbitrarily, and synchronization procedures, which must in fact meet additional criteria, as I have previously shown with reference to sound signals in this and this post.
That is not to say that Einstein did not have any reason to opt for his clock adjustment procedure. The chief reason, it seems, is his stated aim "to arrive at a simple and consistent electrodynamics of moving bodies on the basis of Maxwell's theory for bodies at rest" ("On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies", p. 892). In Maxwell's theory, light travels at c in all directions, and generalizing this theory to all frames of reference therefore requires a clock adjustment procedure which ensures that the speed of light is always identical in opposite directions.
While this may well explain Einstein's choice of clock adjustment procedure, it doesn't make that procedure a synchronization procedure. Indeed, both of the criteria that I have identified for a clock adjustment procedure using Einstein's signalling method to qualify as a synchronization procedure appear to be violated.
First, as observed before, Einstein's clock adjustment procedure leads to the theoretical possibility of signals arriving at their destination before they were emitted.
Second, I have suggested that Einstein's clock adjustment procedure is a synchronization procedure only if the conditions in which the signals propagate are symmetrical in opposite directions. This needs to be qualified a little bit. Strictly speaking this is a sufficient rather than a necessary condition, since it may turn out that signals that do not propagate in identical conditions in opposite directions nevertheless lead to the same clock adjustment if the effects of various parameters that are different in different directions cancel each other out. Nevertheless, I would suggest that equal conditions of signal emission as well as propagation in opposite directions should be made a requirement of any (primary) Einstein-like synchronization procedure so that we can be sure that the signal used is suitable.
But if this condition is fulfilled for particular light signals in a particular frame of reference, then the same light signals cannot be used to synchronize clocks in a second frame of reference that moves relative to the first. Let me illustrate the situation with a diagram:
In this diagram, in a frame of reference in which the laws of mechanics hold, some kind of signal - objects projected by an explosion, sound, light or any other signal - is emitted. This event, represented by the star, occurs just as an observer A in a second frame of reference passes by. Suppose that the conditions in which the signal is emitted and propagates are completely symmetrical in all directions in the first frame of reference, and that thus Einstein's synchronization procedure is applicable, producing equal speeds of propagation in opposite directions in that frame.
My contention is that, regardless of the kind of signal used, the same signal cannot then be used to synchronize clocks in A's frame of reference, since A's movement in one of the directions in which the signal propagates means that the symmetry of the conditions in which it is emitted or propagates is inevitably broken.
Now suppose that the same kind of signal is sent out from A at the same time as the first signal, and that empirically it is found to travel in all directions at the same one-way speed (as defined in this post) as the first signal:
Then the second signal cannot be used to synchronize clocks in A's frame of reference, either, since we already know that the first signal cannot be used. This kind of reasoning is completely uncontroversial in the case of, for example, objects projected by an explosion or sound. Surely light cannot be an exception.
Or can it? In a book published in 1962 in English and two years later in German, the physicist Max Born argues that the absence of a universal light medium, or ether, which was already noted by Einstein in 1905, means that each frame of reference in which the laws of mechanics hold is equivalent to any other as far as the propagation of light is concerned and that therefore Einstein's clock adjustment procedure can function as a synchronization procedure in every frame of reference.
Born's reasoning as set out in his book is one of the most detailed attempts to justify the idea that Einstein's clock adjustment procedure is a synchronization procedure that I have found in the literature. It therefore requires very careful analysis - in my next post.
According to the principle of the constancy of the speed of light in SR, if an observer chases after a flash of light, the light will keep moving away from the observer at the universal speed c no matter how much the observer speeds up. Likewise, if an observer runs into a flash of light, the light will keep moving towards the observer at c no matter how much the observer speeds up.
As I mentioned in a previous post, another consequence of the constancy of c is the possibility of causality paradoxes if hypothetical superluminal signals are considered. But at low speeds, too, there are some surprising effects. For example, if two observers A and B at rest relative to each other at opposite ends of the observable universe started to walk in the same direction A--> B--> at the same time, then, in accordance with the transformations of SR, A would suddenly have to consider that B set out 300 years earlier than A and is now long dead. If both stopped after a few metres, however, B would promptly come back to life as far as A is concerned since A would now consider that A and B set out at the same time, after all, and also stopped at the same time.
All this strangeness is at least partly the making of physicists because, as explained in previous posts, the notions of "simultaneity" and "one-way speed" as defined in SR crucially depend on Einstein's choice of clock adjustment procedure. It is now time to look at the literature on SR to see how physicists have justified such a clock adjustment procedure, and how they have defended the idea that it represents a synchronization procedure that may serve to define simultaneity and one-way speed.
Let me begin with a little survey of the texts I would like to examine. The first two are Albert Einstein's famous 1905 article "On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies" and his subsequent account of the main features of SR intended for a wider audience, first published in 1916. In my opinion, these two publications are much clearer regarding the foundations of special relativity than many other texts published on the subject since. In particular, Einstein is perfectly lucid on the role of convention, definition or stipulation in his theory. On the other hand, there is very little in these texts to motivate or justify his clock adjustment procedure, let alone the idea that it may serve as a synchronization procedure.
This is perhaps unsurprising since, as far as I know, Einstein was addressing an audience whose main concern was to reconcile recent experimental results with the erroneous idea of an essentially static, all-pervasive medium for light, or "ether". He was not writing for future generations of students of physics who had never had any reason to believe in such an "ether" in the first place and were much more interested in the issue of meaningful synchronization procedures.
This is where modern textbooks and other publications focusing on the foundations of special relativity come in. Two which I would like to consider are an online article by Allen Janis wholly dedicated to the issue of the "Conventionality of Simultaneity" in SR, and a 1977 article by Reza Mansouri and Roman U. Sexl on "A Test Theory of Special Relativity: I. Simultaneity and Clock Synchronization". In addition, I have identified four books which are of particular interest to me because of their explicit emphasis on the concepts underlying SR: Leo Sartori's Understanding Relativity (1996); Wolfgang Rindler's Relativity: Special, General, Cosmological (2001); Vesselin Petkov's Relativity and the Nature of Spacetime (2005); and above all Kevin Brown's Reflections on Relativity (2010).
Kevin Brown's book is particularly relevant to my project because it explicitly addresses some of the very same issues I am grappling with in this blog. What is more, it gives a clear, coherent and erudite account of the foundations of SR unrivalled by any of the other texts I have mentioned. If there is hope for my understanding of the principle of the constancy of c, it lies in Kevin Brown's book!
But first things first, so let me start with Brown's illustrious precursor, Albert Einstein - in my next post.